Friday 14 June 2013

Book review- Karl menger by Manish Padhi

Principles of Economics- Karl Menger
THE GENERAL THEORY OF THE GOOD

Things that can be placed in a causal connection with the satisfaction
of human needs we term useful things.1 If, however, we both
recognize this causal connection, and have the power actually to
direct the useful things to the satisfaction of our needs, we call
them goods.2
If a thing is to become a good, or in other words, if it is to
acquire goods-character, all four of the following prerequisites
must be simultaneously present:

1. A human need.
2. Such properties as render the thing capable of being brought
into a causal connection with the satisfaction of this need.
3. Human knowledge of this causal connection.
4. Command of the thing sufficient to direct it to the satisfaction of the good.

The Causal Connections between Goods-

In our own, as in all other sciences, true and lasting progress will be made only
when we no longer regard the objects of our scientific observations
merely as unrelated occurrences, but attempt to discover their
causal connections and the laws to which they are subject. The bread
we eat, the flour from which we bake the bread, the grain that we
mill into flour, and the field on which the grain is grown—all these
things are goods. But knowledge of this fact is not sufficient for our
purposes. On the contrary, it is necessary in the manner of all other
empirical sciences, to attempt to classify the various goods according
to their inherent characteristics, to learn the place that each
good occupies in the causal nexus of goods, and finally, to discover the economic laws to which they are subject.
If we designate the whole sum of goods that are
required to utilize a good of higher order for the production of a good
of first order as its complementary goods in the wider sense of the
term, we obtain the general principle that the goods-character of goods
The General Theory of the Good 61
of higher order depends on our being able to command their complement
goods in this wider sense of the term.

ECONOMY AND ECONOMIC GOODS

The quantities of consumption
goods a person must have to satisfy his needs may be termed his
requirements. The concern of men for the satisfaction of theirs needs thus
becomes an attempt to provide in advance for meeting their requirements
in the future, and we shall therefore call a person’s requirements
those quantities of goods that are necessary to satisfy his
needs within the time period covered by his plans. There are two kinds of knowledge that men must possess as a
prerequisite for any successful attempt to provide in advance for
the satisfaction of their needs. They must become clear: (a) about
their requirements—that is, about the quantities of goods they will
need to satisfy their needs during the time period over which their
plans extend, and (b) about the quantities of goods at their disposal
for the purpose of meeting these requirements. We can
bring quantities of goods of higher order to the production of given quantities
of goods of lower order, and thus finally to the meeting of our
requirements, only if we are in the position of having the complementary
quantities of the other goods of higher order simultaneously at our disposal.

If economizing men
become aware of this circumstance (that is, if they perceive that the
satisfaction of one of their needs, or the greater or less completeness
of its satisfaction, is dependent on their command of each portion
of a quantity of goods or on each individual good subject to
the above quantitative relationship) these goods attain for them
the significance we call value. Value is thus the importance that
individual goods or quantities of goods attain for us because we
are conscious of being dependent on command of them for the satisfaction
of our needs.
Regarding this knowledge, however, men can be in error about
the value of goods just as they can be in error with respect to all
other objects of human knowledge. Hence they may attribute
value to things that do not, according to economic considerations,
possess it in reality, if they mistakenly assume that the
more or less complete satisfaction of their needs depends on a
good, or quantity of goods, when this relationship is really nonexistent.
In cases of this sort we observe the phenomenon of imaginary
value.

The case just presented, in which the needs of two persons
could be better satisfied than before by a mutual transfer of goods
having no value to either of them prior to the exchange, and hence
without economic sacrifice on either side, was especially suitable
for impressing upon us in the most enlightening manner the
nature of the economic relationship leading to trade. But we would
construe this relationship too narrowly if we were to confine our
attention to cases in which a person who has command of a quantity
of one good larger than even his full requirements suffers a
deficiency of a second good, while another person has a comparable
surplus of this second good and a deficiency of the first. For the
relationship in question can also be observed in less obvious cases
in which one person possesses goods of which certain quantities
have less value to him than quantities of another good owned by a
second person who is in the reverse situation.
The two economizing individuals (a) recognize
the situation, and (b) have the power actually to perform the transfer
of the goods, a relationship exists that makes it possible for
them, by a mere agreement, to provide better, or more completely,
for the satisfaction of their needs than would be the case if the relationship
were not exploited.
If the locks between two still bodies of water at different levels
are opened, the surface will become ruffled with waves that will
gradually subside until the water is still once more. The waves are
only symptoms of the operation of the forces we call gravity and
friction. The prices of goods, which are symptoms of an economic
equilibrium in the distribution of possessions between the
economies of individuals, resemble these waves. The force that
drives them to the surface is the ultimate and general cause of all
economic activity, the endeavor of men to satisfy their needs as
completely as possible, to better their economic positions. But
since prices are the only phenomena of the process that are directly
perceptible, since their magnitudes can be measured exactly, and
since daily living brings them unceasingly before our eyes, it was
easy to commit the error of regarding the magnitude of price as the
essential feature of an exchange, and as a result of this mistake, to
commit the further error of regarding the quantities of goods in an
exchange as equivalents. The result was incalculable damage to our
science since writers in the field of price theory lost themselves in
attempts to solve the problem of discovering the causes of an
alleged equality between two quantities of goods.1 Some found the
cause in equal quantities of labor expended on the goods. Others
found it in equal costs of production. And a dispute even arose as
to whether the goods are given for each other because they are
equivalents, or whether they are equivalents because they are
exchanged. But such an equality of the values of two quantities of
goods (an equality in the objective sense) nowhere has any real
existence.

The solution to this question arises from reflection upon the
nature of human economy and upon the nature of value. The
leading idea in all the economic activity of men is the fullest
possible satisfaction of their needs. If more important satisfactions
of an economizing individual are assured by the direct use
of a good than by its indirect use, it follows that more important
needs of the individual would remain unsatisfied if he were to
employ the good in an indirect fashion for the satisfaction of his
needs than if he were to employ it directly. There can be no
doubt that in this case the use value of the good will be determining
in the economic calculations and actions of the economizing
individual concerned, and that in the reverse case it will
be the exchange value. In the first case, it is the satisfactions that
are assured by a direct employment of the good that the economizing
individual would choose if he had command of it; in the
second case, it is the satisfactions that are assured by an indirect
employment of the good that he would choose if he had command
of it; hence in each case it is the satisfactions that would
otherwise have taken place that he would be compelled to
forgo if he did not have command of the good in question.
A further step in the path of economic development to higher
levels of well-being can be regarded as having been taken when
the artisans themselves begin to procure the raw materials for their
products, even though they still produce these products for the
consumers only on order. This state of affairs can still, with few
exceptions, be observed in small towns, and to some extent even in
larger places in some trades. The artisan does not yet manufacture
products for later, and hence uncertain, sale. But he is already, to
the extent of his labor power, in a position to meet the needs of his
customers by making it unnecessary for them to expend efforts on
purchasing or producing raw materials in a frequently highly
uneconomic manner.
But in scientific discourse a need was felt for a term designating
all economic goods held ready for sale without regard to their tangibility,
mobility, or character as products of labour, and without
regard to the persons offering them for sale. A large number of
economists, especially German economists, therefore defined commodities
as (economic) goods of any kind that are intended for sale.
The commodity concept in the popular sense is nevertheless of
importance not only because law-givers3 and a large number of
economists employ the term in the popular sense, but also because
some of those who are aware of the wider, scientific, sense of the
term sometimes employ this or that element of the narrower, popular,
meaning in their definitions.
Money is not the product of an agreement on the part of economizing
men nor the product of legislative acts. No one invented
it. As economizing individuals in social situations became
increasingly aware of their economic interest, they everywhere
attained the simple knowledge that surrendering less saleable
commodities for others of greater saleability brings them substantially
closer to the attainment of their specific economic
purposes. Thus, with the progressive development of social
economy, money came to exist in numerous centers of civilization
independently. But precisely because money is a natural
product of human economy, the specific forms in which it has appeared were everywhere and at all times the result of specific
and changing economic situations. Among the same people at different
times, and among different peoples at the same time, different
goods have attained the special position in trade described
above.
As the price of a commodity is the average cost of production, it includes the fact that a tiny proportion of commodities may be found, although finding goods is hardly typical of modern manufacturing processes.
Marginal utility as the source of value meant that the perceived need for an object was seen to be dictating the value, on an individual rather than a general level. The implication was that the individual mind is the source of economic value.
Although Menger accepted the marginal utility theory, he made deviations from the work of other neoclassical pioneers. Most importantly he fundamentally rejected the use of mathematical methods insisting that the function of economics was to investigate the essences rather than the specific quantities of economic phenomena.


No comments:

Post a Comment